Aileen Kavanagh. (2003). Participation and Judicial Review: A Reply to Jeremy Waldron. Law and Philosophy, 22(5), 451–486. http://www.jstor.org/stable/3505148
Allen Buchanan. (2002). Political Legitimacy and Democracy. Ethics, 112(4), 689–719. https://doi.org/10.1086/340313
Alon Harel. (2003). Rights-Based Judicial Review: A Democratic Justification. Law and Philosophy, 22(3), 247–276. http://www.jstor.org/stable/3505108
Alvin I. Goldman. (1999). Why Citizens Should Vote: A Causal Responsibility Approach. Social Philosophy and Policy, 16(02), 201–217. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0265052500002442
Andrew Sabl. (2001). Looking Forward to Justice: Rawlsian Civil Disobedience and its Non-Rawlsian Lessons. Journal of Political Philosophy, 9(3), 307–330. https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-9760.00129
Annabelle Lever. (2009). Democracy and Judicial Review: Are They Really Incompatible? Perspectives on Politics, 7(04). https://doi.org/10.1017/S1537592709991812
Anne Phillips. (1991). Engendering democracy. Polity Press.
Anne Phillips. (1992). Must Feminists Give up on Liberal Democracy? Political Studies, 40(1_suppl), 68–82. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9248.1992.tb01813.x
Arash Abizadeh. (2008). Democratic Theory and Border Coercion. Political Theory, 36(1), 37–65. https://doi.org/10.1177/0090591707310090
Arneson, R. J. (1982). The Principle of Fairness and Free-Rider Problems. Ethics, 92(4), 616–633. https://doi.org/10.1086/292379
Arthur Ripstein. (2004). Authority and Coercion. Philosophy Public Affairs, 32(1), 2–35. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-6486.2004.00003.x
Barry, B. (1991). Is Democracy Special? in Democracy and power: essays in political theory I. Clarendon Press.
Beerbohm, E. A. (2012). Democratic Complicity (Chapter 9). In In our name: the ethics of democracy (pp. 226–251). Princeton University Press. http://www.jstor.org/stable/10.2307/j.ctt7rtcj
Beran, H. (1987). The consent theory of political obligation: Vol. Croom Helm international series in social and political thought. Croom Helm.
Bernard Boxill. (1976). Self-Respect and Protest. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 6(1), 58–69. http://www.jstor.org/stable/2265062
Bernard R. Boxill. (2010). The Responsibility of the Oppressed to Resist Their Own Oppression. Journal of Social Philosophy, 41(1), 1–12. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9833.2009.01474.x
Bhikhu Parekh. (1993). A Misconceived Discourse on Political Obligation. Political Studies, 41(2), 236–251. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9248.2006.tb00926.x
Brennan, J. (2012). The ethics of voting. Princeton University Press. http://www.jstor.org/stable/10.2307/j.ctt7rt0m
C. A. J. Coady. (2008). Chapters 2 and 3 in Morality and political violence. In Morality and Political Violence. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511811586
Candice Delmas. (2014). Political Resistance: A Matter of Fairness. Law and Philosophy, 33(4), 465–488. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10982-013-9189-y
Carol Hay. (2011). The Obligation to Resist Oppression. Journal of Social Philosophy, 42(1), 21–45. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9833.2010.01518.x
Caygill, H. (2013). On resistance: a philosophy of defiance. Bloomsbury Academic.
Cecile Fabre. (2000). A Philosophical Argument for a Bill of Rights. British Journal of Political Science, 30(1), 77–98. https://www.jstor.org/stable/194114
Cheney Ryan. (2017). Bearers of Hope: On the Paradox of Non-Violent Action. In Michael L. Gross & Tamar Meisels (Eds.), Soft war: the ethics of unarmed conflict (pp. 166–183). Cambridge University Press. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316450802
Christiano, T. (1996). Chapter 5 & 7 in The rule of the many: fundamental issues in democratic theory: Vol. Focus (Southern Regional Education Board). Westview Press.
Christiano, T. (2004). The Authority of Democracy*. Journal of Political Philosophy, 12(3), 266–290. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9760.2004.00200.x
Christiano, T. (2008). Chapter 7 in The constitution of equality: democratic authority and its limits. Oxford University Press.
Christopher G. Griffin. (2003). Democracy as a Non-Instrumentally Just Procedure. Journal of Political Philosophy, 11(1), 111–121. https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-9760.00169
Christopher Kutz. (2002). The Collective Work of Citizenship. Legal Theory, 8(04), 471–494. https://www.cambridge.org/core/journals/legal-theory/article/collective-work-of-citizenship/689B3781BD61E8A8C06D51D462FE306E
Corey Brettschneider. (2005). Balancing Procedures and Outcomes within Democratic Theory: Core Values and Judicial Review. Political Studies, 53(2), 423–441. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9248.2005.00536.x
Cudd, A. E. (2006). Analyzing oppression: Vol. Studies in feminist philosophy. Oxford University Press. http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/0195187431.001.0001
Cynthia A. Stark. (2000). Hypothetical Consent and Justification. The Journal of Philosophy, 97(6), 313–344. http://www.jstor.org/stable/2678406
Dagger, R. (1997). Chapter 9 in Civic virtues: rights, citizenship, and republican liberalism: Vol. Oxford political theory. Oxford University Press.
Dahl, R. A. (1989). Democracy and its critics. Yale University Press.
Daniel Markovits. (2005). Democratic Disobedience. The Yale Law Journal, 114(8), 1897–1952. http://www.jstor.org/stable/4135751
Daniel Silvermint. (2013). Resistance and Well-being. Journal of Political Philosophy, 21(4), 405–425. https://doi.org/10.1111/jopp.12002
David Brooks. (1989). On Living in an Unjust Society. Journal of Applied Philosophy, 6(1), 31–42. http://www.jstor.org/stable/24353341
David Enoch. (2002). Some Arguments Against Conscientious Objection and Civil Disobedience Refuted. Israel Law Review, 36(03), 227–253. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0021223700018045
David Lefkowitz. (2007). On a Moral Right to Civil Disobedience. Ethics, 117(2), 202–233. https://doi.org/10.1086/510694
David Lyons. (1998). Moral Judgment, Historical Reality, and Civil Disobedience. Philosophy Public Affairs, 27(1), 31–49. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1088-4963.1998.tb00058.x
David Miller. (1988). The Ethical Significance of Nationality. Ethics, 98(4), 647–662. https://doi.org/10.1086/292997
David Miller. (2001). Territorial Boundaries: A Liberal-Egalitarian Perspective. In Boundaries and justice: diverse ethical perspectives: Vol. Ethikon series in comparative ethics (pp. 249–275). Princeton University Press. https://www.jstor.org/stable/j.ctv1h9dj5p
David Miller. (2009). Democracy’s Domain. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 37(3), 201–228. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1088-4963.2009.01158.x
David Miller. (2010). Why Immigration Controls Are Not Coercive: A Reply to Arash Abizadeh. Political Theory, 38(1), 111–120. https://doi.org/10.1177/0090591709348194
Dworkin, R. (1985). Civil Disobedience and Nuclear Protest. In A matter of principle. Harvard University Press.
Dworkin, R. (2011). Justice for hedgehogs. Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.
Dworkin, R. (2013). Taking rights seriously. Bloomsbury Academic.
Ely, J. H. (1980). Democracy and distrust: A theory of judicial review. Harvard University Press.
Estlund, D. M. (2008). Normative Consent. In Democratic authority: a philosophical framework. Princeton University Press. http://www.vlebooks.com/vleweb/product/openreader?id=UCL&isbn=9781400831548
Fanon, F. (1963). Concerning Violence. In The Wretched of the Earth. http://abahlali.org/wp-content/uploads/2011/04/Frantz-Fanon-The-Wretched-of-the-Earth-1965.pdf
Fine, S. (2016). Immigration and Discrimination. In S. Fine & L. Ypi (Eds.), Migration in political theory: the ethics of movement and membership (First edition). Oxford University Press. http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199676606.001.0001
Frazer, E., & Hutchings, K. (2008). On Politics and Violence: Arendt Contra Fanon. Contemporary Political Theory, 7(1), 90–108. https://doi.org/10.1057/palgrave.cpt.9300328
George Klosko. (1987). Presumptive Benefit, Fairness, and Political Obligation. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 16(3), 241–259. http://www.jstor.org/stable/2265266
Gerhard Øverland & Christian Barry. (2011). Do Democratic Societies Have a Right to Do Wrong? Journal of Social Philosophy, 42(2), 111–131. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9833.2011.01524.x
Gordon Graham. (1983). What is Special About Democracy? Mind, XCII(365), 94–102. https://doi.org/10.1093/mind/XCII.365.94
Greenawalt, K. (1987). Conflicts of law and morality. Oxford University Press.
GUERRERO, A. A. (2010). The Paradox of Voting and the Ethics of Political Representation. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 38(3), 272–306. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1088-4963.2010.01188.x
Hanna Pitkin. (1965). Obligation and Consent—I. American Political Science Review, 59(04), 990–999. https://doi.org/10.2307/1953218
Hanna Pitkin. (1966). Obligation and Consent—II. American Political Science Review, 60(01), 39–52. https://doi.org/10.2307/1953805
Harry G. Frankfurt. (1973). The Anarchism of Robert Paul Wolff. Political Theory, 1(4), 405–414. http://www.jstor.org/stable/191060
Honohan, I. (2002). Civic republicanism: Vol. Problems of philosophy series. Routledge.
Horton, J. (1992a). Political obligation: Vol. Issues in political theory. Macmillan.
Horton, J. (1992b). Political obligation: Vol. Issues in political theory. Macmillan.
Hugo Adam Bedau. (1970). Civil Disobedience and Personal Responsibility for Injustice. Monist, 54(4), 517–535. https://doi.org/10.5840/monist197054432
Jeff McMahan. (2005). The Basis of Moral Liability to Defensive Killing. Philosophical Issues, 15(1), 386–405. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1533-6077.2005.00073.x
John Morreall. (1976). The Justifiability of Violent Civil Disobedience. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 6(1), 35–47. https://doi.org/10.1080/00455091.1976.10716975
Joseph Raz. (1985). Authority and Justification. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 14(1), 3–29. http://www.jstor.org/stable/2265235
Keith Dowding, Robert E. Goodin, & Carole Pateman (Eds.). (2004). Justice and Democracy: Essays for Brian Barry. Cambridge University Press. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511490217
Kimberley Brownlee. (2012). Conscience and Conviction. Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199592944.001.0001
Klosko, G. (2004). The principle of fairness and political obligation: Vol. Studies in social, political, and legal philosophy (New ed). Rowman & Littlefield.
Larry Alexander. (2006). What is the problem with judicial review? Australian Journal of Legal Philosophy, 31, 1–13. https://heinonline.org/HOL/P?h=hein.journals/ajlph31&i=5
Laslett, P., Runciman, W. G., Skinner, Q., & Tuck, R. (1972). Why is Authority Such a Problem? in Philosophy, politics and society: 4th series. Blackwell.
Laura Valentini. (2013). Justice, Disagreement and Democracy. British Journal of Political Science, 43(01), 177–199. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0007123412000294
Lorde, A. (2007). The Transformation of Silence into Language and Action. In Sister outsider: essays and speeches (Revised edition). Crossing Press.
Loren E. Lomasky & Geoffrey Brennan. (2000). Is there a Duty to Vote? Social Philosophy and Policy, 17(01), 62–86. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0265052500002533
M. B. E. Smith. (1973). Is There a Prima Facie Obligation to Obey the Law? The Yale Law Journal, 82(5), 950–976. https://doi.org/10.2307/795537
Macedo, S. (2010). Against Majoritarianism: Democratic Values and Institutional Design. Boston University Law Review. http://heinonline.org/HOL/Page?public=false&handle=hein.journals/bulr90&id=1035
Margaret Gilbert. (1999). Reconsidering the "Actual Contract” Theory of Political Obligation. Ethics, 109(2), 236–260. https://doi.org/10.1086/233895
Martin Luther King. (n.d.-a). The Power of Non-violence, speech from 1957. Teaching American History. http://teachingamericanhistory.org/library/document/the-power-of-non-violence/
Martin Luther King Jr. (n.d.-b). Letter from a Birmingham Jail [King, Jr.]. African Studies Center - University of Pennsylvania. https://www.africa.upenn.edu/Articles_Gen/Letter_Birmingham.html
McDermott, D. (2004). Fair-Play Obligations. Political Studies, 52(2), 216–232. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9248.2004.00476.x
Michael, Walzer. (1983). Three Distributive Principles. In Spheres of justice: a defence of pluralism and equality (pp. 21–26). Robertson. https://contentstore.cla.co.uk/secure/link?id=84b43892-4333-ed11-bd6e-0050f2f06092
Miller, D. (1984). Anarchism: Vol. Modern ideologies. Dent.
Miller, D. (2016). Strangers in our midst: the political philosophy of immigration. Harvard University Press. http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/ucl/detail.action?docID=4515684
Miller, D., Siedentop, L., & Jones, P. (1983). Political Equality and Majority Rule in The nature of political theory. Clarendon.
Mohandas Gandhi, author. Anthony J. Parel, editor of compilation. (n.d.). Indian Home Rule [or Hind Swaraj] in Gandhi: ‘Hind Swaraj’ and Other Writings / Mohandas Gandhi, Edited by Anthony J. Parel. http://gandhiserve.org/cwmg/VOL010.PDF
Moraro, P. (2007). Violent Civil Disobedience and Willingness to Accept Punishment. Essays in Philosophy, 8(2). https://commons.pacificu.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1277&context=eip
Nelson Mandela. (1973). The Rivonia Trial. In No easy walk to freedom: articles, speeches and trial addresses of Nelson Mandela (pp. 162–189). Heinemann Educational. https://contentstore.cla.co.uk/secure/link?id=ab43bf1b-9532-ed11-bd6e-0050f2f06092
Noveck, Scott M. (2008). Is Judicial Review Compatible with Democracy? Cardozo Public Law, Policy & Ethics Journal, 6(2). https://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=1019202#%23
Nozick, R. (1974). Anarchy, state, and Utopia. Blackwell.
Nussbaum, M. C., Cohen, J., & Nussbaum, M. (1996). For Love of Country? Debating the Limits of Patriotism’ in For love of country: debating the limits of patriotism. Beacon Press.
Pateman, C. (1988). The sexual contract. Polity.
Pateman, C., & Mills, C. W. (2007). Contract and domination. Polity Press.
Patterson, D. M., Wiley InterScience (Online service), & Gutmann, A. (2010). Democracy in A companion to philosophy of law and legal theory: Vol. Blackwell Companions to Philosophy (2nd ed). Wiley-Blackwell. http://dx.doi.org/10.1002/9781444320114
Quinton, A. (1967). chs. 21 and 22; reprinted as ‘Two Concepts of Democracy in Political philosophy: Vol. Oxford readings in philosophy. Oxford University Press.
Rawls, J. (1999). Chapter VII sections 55-59. In A theory of justice (Rev. ed). Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.
Raz, J. (2009). The authority of law: essays on law and morality (2nd ed). Oxford University Press.
Richard B. Friedman. (1990). On the Concept of Authority in Political Philosophy. In Authority (pp. 56–91). New York University Press.
Richard J. Arneson. (2003). Defending the Purely Instrumental Account of Democratic Legitimacy. Journal of Political Philosophy, 11(1), 122–132. https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-9760.00170
Roberts, A., & Garton Ash, T. (2011). Civil resistance and power politics: the experience of non-violent action from Gandhi to the present. Oxford University Press.
Sabl, A. (2001). Looking Forward to Justice: Rawlsian Civil Disobedience and its Non-Rawlsian Lessons. Journal of Political Philosophy, 9(3), 307–330. https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-9760.00129
Sanders, J. T., Narveson, J., & Simmons, A. J. (1996). Philosophical Anarchism in For and against the state: new philosophical readings: Vol. Studies in social, political, and legal philosophy. Rowman & Littlefield.
Sanders, J. T., Narveson, J., & Wolff, J. (1996). Anarchism and Skepticism’ in For and against the state: new philosophical readings: Vol. Studies in social, political, and legal philosophy. Rowman & Littlefield.
Scheffler, S. (2001). Individual Responsibility in a Global Age. In Boundaries and allegiances: problems of justice and responsibility in liberal thought. Oxford University Press. http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/0199257671.001.0001
Sheehy, P. (2002). A Duty Not to Vote. Ratio, 15(1), 46–57. https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-9329.00175
Shelby, T. (2016). Dark ghettos: injustice, dissent, and reform. The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.
Shute, S., Hurley, S. L., & Elster, J. (1993). Majority rule and individual rights’ in On human rights: the Oxford Amnesty lectures 1993. Basic Books.
Simmons, A. J. (1979a). ch. VIII Moral principles and political obligations. Princeton University Press.
Simmons, A. J. (1979b). Moral principles and political obligations. Princeton University Press.
Simmons, A. J. (2001). Fair Play and Political Obligation: Twenty Years Later. In Justification and legitimacy: essays on rights and obligations. Cambridge University Press.
Singer, P. (1973a). Democracy and disobedience. Clarendon Press.
Singer, P. (1973b). Democracy and disobedience. Clarendon Press.
Sofia Näsström. (2011). The Challenge of the All-Affected Principle. Political Studies, 59(1), 116–134. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9248.2010.00845.x
Swift, A. (2006). Political philosophy: a beginners’ guide for students and politicians (2nd ed., rev.expanded). Polity.
Ted. Honderich Ted Honderich. (n.d.). Violence for equality : inquiries in political philosophy / Ted Honderich. http://ucl-primo.hosted.exlibrisgroup.com/primo_library/libweb/action/display.do?tabs=detailsTab&ct=display&fn=search&doc=UCL_LMS_DS000079578&indx=1&recIds=UCL_LMS_DS000079578&recIdxs=0&elementId=0&renderMode=poppedOut&displayMode=full&frbrVersion=&frbg=&&dscnt=0&scp.scps=scope%3A%28UCL%29%2Cprimo_central_multiple_fe&tb=t&mode=Basic&vid=UCL_VU1&srt=rank&tab=local&dum=true&vl(freeText0)=Violence%20for%20Equality%3A%20Inquiries%20in%20Political%20Philosophy&dstmp=1501678797980
Thomas, Christiano. (2001). Democracy as Equality. In David, Estlund (Ed.), Democracy (pp. 31–50). Blackwell. https://contentstore.cla.co.uk/secure/link?id=ab47e4c3-5ba1-ed11-ac20-0050f2f06092
Thomas Christiano. (2004). The Authority of Democracy. Journal of Political Philosophy, 12(3), 266–290. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9760.2004.00200.x
Thomas E. Hill,. (1973). Servility and Self-Respect. Monist, 57(1), 87–104. https://doi.org/10.5840/monist197357135
Thomas E. Jr Hill. (1991). Symbolic protest and calculated silence. In Autonomy and self-respect (pp. 52–66). Cambridge University Press. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511609237
Thoreau, H. D. (1849). Civil Disobedience. https://www.walden.org/web/viewer.html?file=https://www.walden.org/wp-content/uploads/2016/03/CivilDisobedience.pdf
Tommie Shelby. (2007). Justice, Deviance, and the Dark Ghetto. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 35(2), 126–160. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1088-4963.2007.00106.x
Vinit Haksar. (1976). Rawls and Gandhi on civil disobedience. Inquiry, 19(1–4), 151–192. https://doi.org/10.1080/00201747608601790
Vinit Haksar. (2012). Violence in a spirit of love: Gandhi and the limits of non-violence. Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy, 15(3), 303–324. https://doi.org/10.1080/13698230.2011.644422
Vittorio Bufacchi. (2007). Exploitation, Injustice and Violence. In Violence and social justice (pp. 145–163). Palgrave Macmillan. https://link.springer.com/chapter/10.1057/9780230246416_9
Waldron, J. (1999a). Part III in Law and disagreement. Clarendon Press.
Waldron, J. (1999b). The Constitutional Conception of Democracy. In Law and disagreement. Clarendon Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198262138.001.0001
Waldron, J. (2006). The Core of the Case against Judicial Review. Yale Law Journal. http://heinonline.org/HOL/Page?public=false&handle=hein.journals/ylr115&id=1366
Walzer, M. (1970a). Part 1 in Obligations: essays on disobedience. In Obligations: essays on disobedience, war, and citizenship. Harvard University Press.
Walzer, M. (1970b). The Obligation to Disobey’ and ‘‘The Obligations of Oppressed Minorities’ in Obligations: essays on disobedience, war, and citizenship. Harvard University Press.
Weale, A. (2007a). Chapter 1 in Democracy: Vol. Issues in political theory (2nd ed). Palgrave Macmillan.
Weale, A. (2007b). Chapter 8 in Democracy: Vol. Issues in political theory (2nd ed). Palgrave Macmillan.
Wolff, R. P. (1976). 'The Conflict Between Authority and Autonomy’ (Part One of his book In Defense of Anarchism): Vol. Harper essays in philosophy. Harper & Row. http://www.ditext.com/wolff/anarchy.html
Young, I. M. (2011). The Social Connection Model. In Responsibility for Justice. Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780195392388.001.0001