Aileen Kavanagh (2003) ‘Participation and Judicial Review: A Reply to Jeremy Waldron’, Law and Philosophy, 22(5), pp. 451–486. Available at: http://www.jstor.org/stable/3505148.
Allen Buchanan (2002) ‘Political Legitimacy and Democracy’, Ethics, 112(4), pp. 689–719. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1086/340313.
Alon Harel (2003) ‘Rights-Based Judicial Review: A Democratic Justification’, Law and Philosophy, 22(3), pp. 247–276. Available at: http://www.jstor.org/stable/3505108.
Alvin I. Goldman (1999) ‘Why Citizens Should Vote: A Causal Responsibility Approach’, Social Philosophy and Policy, 16(02), pp. 201–217. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1017/S0265052500002442.
Andrew Sabl (2001) ‘Looking Forward to Justice: Rawlsian Civil Disobedience and its Non-Rawlsian Lessons’, Journal of Political Philosophy, 9(3), pp. 307–330. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-9760.00129.
Annabelle Lever (2009) ‘Democracy and Judicial Review: Are They Really Incompatible?’, Perspectives on Politics, 7(04). Available at: https://doi.org/10.1017/S1537592709991812.
Anne Phillips (1991) Engendering democracy. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Anne Phillips (1992) ‘Must Feminists Give up on Liberal Democracy?’, Political Studies, 40(1_suppl), pp. 68–82. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9248.1992.tb01813.x.
Arash Abizadeh (2008) ‘Democratic Theory and Border Coercion’, Political Theory, 36(1), pp. 37–65. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1177/0090591707310090.
Arneson, R.J. (1982) ‘The Principle of Fairness and Free-Rider Problems’, Ethics, 92(4), pp. 616–633. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1086/292379.
Arthur Ripstein (2004) ‘Authority and Coercion’, Philosophy Public Affairs, 32(1), pp. 2–35. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-6486.2004.00003.x.
Barry, B. (1991) ‘Is Democracy Special? in Democracy and power: essays in political theory I’, in. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Beerbohm, E.A. (2012) ‘Democratic Complicity (Chapter 9)’, in In our name: the ethics of democracy. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, pp. 226–251. Available at: http://www.jstor.org/stable/10.2307/j.ctt7rtcj.
Beran, H. (1987) The consent theory of political obligation. London: Croom Helm.
Bernard Boxill (1976) ‘Self-Respect and Protest’, Philosophy & Public Affairs, 6(1), pp. 58–69. Available at: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2265062.
Bernard R. Boxill (2010) ‘The Responsibility of the Oppressed to Resist Their Own Oppression’, Journal of Social Philosophy, 41(1), pp. 1–12. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9833.2009.01474.x.
Bhikhu Parekh (1993) ‘A Misconceived Discourse on Political Obligation’, Political Studies, 41(2), pp. 236–251. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9248.2006.tb00926.x.
Brennan, J. (2012) The ethics of voting. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Available at: http://www.jstor.org/stable/10.2307/j.ctt7rt0m.
C. A. J. Coady (2008) ‘Chapters 2 and 3 in Morality and political violence’, in Morality and Political Violence. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511811586.
Candice Delmas (2014) ‘Political Resistance: A Matter of Fairness’, Law and Philosophy, 33(4), pp. 465–488. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10982-013-9189-y.
Carol Hay (2011) ‘The Obligation to Resist Oppression’, Journal of Social Philosophy, 42(1), pp. 21–45. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9833.2010.01518.x.
Caygill, H. (2013) On resistance: a philosophy of defiance. London: Bloomsbury Academic.
Cecile Fabre (2000) ‘A Philosophical Argument for a Bill of Rights’, British Journal of Political Science, 30(1), pp. 77–98. Available at: https://www.jstor.org/stable/194114.
Cheney Ryan (2017) ‘Bearers of Hope: On the Paradox of Non-Violent Action’, in Michael L. Gross and Tamar Meisels (eds) Soft war: the ethics of unarmed conflict. Cambridge, United Kingdom: Cambridge University Press, pp. 166–183. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316450802.
Christiano, T. (1996) ‘Chapter 5 & 7 in The rule of the many: fundamental issues in democratic theory’, in. Boulder, Colo: Westview Press.
Christiano, T. (2004) ‘The Authority of Democracy*’, Journal of Political Philosophy, 12(3), pp. 266–290. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9760.2004.00200.x.
Christiano, T. (2008) ‘Chapter 7 in The constitution of equality: democratic authority and its limits’, in. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Christopher G. Griffin (2003) ‘Democracy as a Non-Instrumentally Just Procedure’, Journal of Political Philosophy, 11(1), pp. 111–121. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-9760.00169.
Christopher Kutz (2002) ‘The Collective Work of Citizenship’, Legal Theory, 8(04), pp. 471–494. Available at: https://www.cambridge.org/core/journals/legal-theory/article/collective-work-of-citizenship/689B3781BD61E8A8C06D51D462FE306E.
Corey Brettschneider (2005) ‘Balancing Procedures and Outcomes within Democratic Theory: Core Values and Judicial Review’, Political Studies, 53(2), pp. 423–441. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9248.2005.00536.x.
Cudd, A.E. (2006) Analyzing oppression. New York, N.Y.: Oxford University Press. Available at: http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/0195187431.001.0001.
Cynthia A. Stark (2000) ‘Hypothetical Consent and Justification’, The Journal of Philosophy, 97(6), pp. 313–344. Available at: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2678406.
Dagger, R. (1997) ‘Chapter 9 in Civic virtues: rights, citizenship, and republican liberalism’, in. New York: Oxford University Press.
Dahl, R.A. (1989) Democracy and its critics. New Haven: Yale University Press.
Daniel Markovits (2005) ‘Democratic Disobedience’, The Yale Law Journal, 114(8), pp. 1897–1952. Available at: http://www.jstor.org/stable/4135751.
Daniel Silvermint (2013) ‘Resistance and Well-being’, Journal of Political Philosophy, 21(4), pp. 405–425. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1111/jopp.12002.
David Brooks (1989) ‘On Living in an Unjust Society’, Journal of Applied Philosophy, 6(1), pp. 31–42. Available at: http://www.jstor.org/stable/24353341.
David Enoch (2002) ‘Some Arguments Against Conscientious Objection and Civil Disobedience Refuted’, Israel Law Review, 36(03), pp. 227–253. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1017/S0021223700018045.
David Lefkowitz (2007) ‘On a Moral Right to Civil Disobedience’, Ethics, 117(2), pp. 202–233. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1086/510694.
David Lyons (1998) ‘Moral Judgment, Historical Reality, and Civil Disobedience’, Philosophy Public Affairs, 27(1), pp. 31–49. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1088-4963.1998.tb00058.x.
David Miller (1988) ‘The Ethical Significance of Nationality’, Ethics, 98(4), pp. 647–662. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1086/292997.
David Miller (2001) ‘Territorial Boundaries: A Liberal-Egalitarian Perspective’, in Boundaries and justice: diverse ethical perspectives. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, pp. 249–275. Available at: https://www.jstor.org/stable/j.ctv1h9dj5p.
David Miller (2009) ‘Democracy’s Domain’, Philosophy & Public Affairs, 37(3), pp. 201–228. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1088-4963.2009.01158.x.
David Miller (2010) ‘Why Immigration Controls Are Not Coercive: A Reply to Arash Abizadeh’, Political Theory, 38(1), pp. 111–120. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1177/0090591709348194.
Dworkin, R. (1985) ‘Civil Disobedience and Nuclear Protest’, in A matter of principle. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press.
Dworkin, R. (2011) Justice for hedgehogs. Cambridge, Mass: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.
Dworkin, R. (2013) Taking rights seriously. London: Bloomsbury Academic.
Ely, J.H. (1980) Democracy and distrust: A theory of judicial review. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press.
Estlund, D.M. (2008) ‘Normative Consent’, in Democratic authority: a philosophical framework. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Available at: http://www.vlebooks.com/vleweb/product/openreader?id=UCL&isbn=9781400831548.
Fanon, F. (1963) ‘Concerning Violence’, in The Wretched of the Earth. Available at: http://abahlali.org/wp-content/uploads/2011/04/Frantz-Fanon-The-Wretched-of-the-Earth-1965.pdf.
Fine, S. (2016) ‘Immigration and Discrimination’, in S. Fine and L. Ypi (eds) Migration in political theory: the ethics of movement and membership. First edition. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Available at: http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199676606.001.0001.
Frazer, E. and Hutchings, K. (2008) ‘On Politics and Violence: Arendt Contra Fanon’, Contemporary Political Theory, 7(1), pp. 90–108. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1057/palgrave.cpt.9300328.
George Klosko (1987) ‘Presumptive Benefit, Fairness, and Political Obligation’, Philosophy & Public Affairs, 16(3), pp. 241–259. Available at: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2265266.
Gerhard Øverland and Christian Barry (2011) ‘Do Democratic Societies Have a Right to Do Wrong?’, Journal of Social Philosophy, 42(2), pp. 111–131. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9833.2011.01524.x.
Gordon Graham (1983) ‘What is Special About Democracy?’, Mind, XCII(365), pp. 94–102. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1093/mind/XCII.365.94.
Greenawalt, K. (1987) Conflicts of law and morality. New York: Oxford University Press.
GUERRERO, A.A. (2010) ‘The Paradox of Voting and the Ethics of Political Representation’, Philosophy & Public Affairs, 38(3), pp. 272–306. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1088-4963.2010.01188.x.
Hanna Pitkin (1965) ‘Obligation and Consent—I.’, American Political Science Review, 59(04), pp. 990–999. Available at: https://doi.org/10.2307/1953218.
Hanna Pitkin (1966) ‘Obligation and Consent—II’, American Political Science Review, 60(01), pp. 39–52. Available at: https://doi.org/10.2307/1953805.
Harry G. Frankfurt (1973) ‘The Anarchism of Robert Paul Wolff’, Political Theory, 1(4), pp. 405–414. Available at: http://www.jstor.org/stable/191060.
Honohan, I. (2002) Civic republicanism. London: Routledge.
Horton, J. (1992a) Political obligation. Basingstoke: Macmillan.
Horton, J. (1992b) Political obligation. Basingstoke: Macmillan.
Hugo Adam Bedau (1970) ‘Civil Disobedience and Personal Responsibility for Injustice’, Monist, 54(4), pp. 517–535. Available at: https://doi.org/10.5840/monist197054432.
Jeff McMahan (2005) ‘The Basis of Moral Liability to Defensive Killing’, Philosophical Issues, 15(1), pp. 386–405. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1533-6077.2005.00073.x.
John Morreall (1976) ‘The Justifiability of Violent Civil Disobedience’, Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 6(1), pp. 35–47. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1080/00455091.1976.10716975.
Joseph Raz (1985) ‘Authority and Justification’, Philosophy & Public Affairs, 14(1), pp. 3–29. Available at: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2265235.
Keith Dowding, Robert E. Goodin, and Carole Pateman (eds) (2004) Justice and Democracy: Essays for Brian Barry. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Available at: http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511490217.
Kimberley Brownlee (2012) Conscience and Conviction. Oxford University Press. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199592944.001.0001.
Klosko, G. (2004) The principle of fairness and political obligation. New ed. Lanham, Md: Rowman & Littlefield.
Larry Alexander (2006) ‘What is the problem with judicial review?’, Australian Journal of Legal Philosophy, 31, pp. 1–13. Available at: https://heinonline.org/HOL/P?h=hein.journals/ajlph31&i=5.
Laslett, P. et al. (1972) ‘Why is Authority Such a Problem? in Philosophy, politics and society: 4th series’, in. Oxford: Blackwell.
Laura Valentini (2013) ‘Justice, Disagreement and Democracy’, British Journal of Political Science, 43(01), pp. 177–199. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1017/S0007123412000294.
Lorde, A. (2007) ‘The Transformation of Silence into Language and Action’, in Sister outsider: essays and speeches. Revised edition. Berkeley: Crossing Press.
Loren E. Lomasky and Geoffrey Brennan (2000) ‘Is there a Duty to Vote?’, Social Philosophy and Policy, 17(01), pp. 62–86. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1017/S0265052500002533.
M. B. E. Smith (1973) ‘Is There a Prima Facie Obligation to Obey the Law?’, The Yale Law Journal, 82(5), pp. 950–976. Available at: https://doi.org/10.2307/795537.
Macedo, S. (2010) ‘Against Majoritarianism: Democratic Values and Institutional Design’, Boston University Law Review [Preprint]. Available at: http://heinonline.org/HOL/Page?public=false&handle=hein.journals/bulr90&id=1035.
Margaret Gilbert (1999) ‘Reconsidering the "Actual Contract” Theory of Political Obligation’, Ethics, 109(2), pp. 236–260. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1086/233895.
Martin Luther King (no date) The Power of Non-violence, speech from 1957. Teaching American History. Available at: http://teachingamericanhistory.org/library/document/the-power-of-non-violence/.
Martin Luther King Jr (no date) Letter from a Birmingham Jail [King, Jr.]. African Studies Center - University of Pennsylvania. Available at: https://www.africa.upenn.edu/Articles_Gen/Letter_Birmingham.html.
McDermott, D. (2004) ‘Fair-Play Obligations’, Political Studies, 52(2), pp. 216–232. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9248.2004.00476.x.
Michael, Walzer (1983) ‘Three Distributive Principles’, in Spheres of justice: a defence of pluralism and equality. Oxford: Robertson, pp. 21–26. Available at: https://contentstore.cla.co.uk/secure/link?id=84b43892-4333-ed11-bd6e-0050f2f06092.
Miller, D. (1984) Anarchism. London: Dent.
Miller, D. (2016) Strangers in our midst: the political philosophy of immigration. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press. Available at: http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/ucl/detail.action?docID=4515684.
Miller, D., Siedentop, L. and Jones, P. (1983) ‘Political Equality and Majority Rule in The nature of political theory’, in. Oxford: Clarendon.
Mohandas Gandhi, author. Anthony J. Parel, editor of compilation. (no date) ‘Indian Home Rule [or Hind Swaraj] in Gandhi: “Hind Swaraj” and Other Writings / Mohandas Gandhi, Edited by Anthony J. Parel.’, in. Available at: http://gandhiserve.org/cwmg/VOL010.PDF.
Moraro, P. (2007) ‘Violent Civil Disobedience and Willingness to Accept Punishment’, Essays in Philosophy, 8(2). Available at: https://commons.pacificu.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1277&context=eip.
Nelson Mandela (1973) ‘The Rivonia Trial’, in No easy walk to freedom: articles, speeches and trial addresses of Nelson Mandela. London: Heinemann Educational, pp. 162–189. Available at: https://contentstore.cla.co.uk/secure/link?id=ab43bf1b-9532-ed11-bd6e-0050f2f06092.
Noveck, Scott M. (2008) ‘Is Judicial Review Compatible with Democracy?’, Cardozo Public Law, Policy & Ethics Journal, 6(2). Available at: https://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=1019202#%23.
Nozick, R. (1974) Anarchy, state, and Utopia. Malden, MA: Blackwell.
Nussbaum, M.C., Cohen, J. and Nussbaum, M. (1996) ‘For Love of Country? Debating the Limits of Patriotism’ in For love of country: debating the limits of patriotism’, in. Boston: Beacon Press.
Pateman, C. (1988) The sexual contract. Cambridge: Polity.
Pateman, C. and Mills, C.W. (2007) Contract and domination. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Patterson, D.M., Wiley InterScience (Online service) and Gutmann, A. (2010) ‘Democracy in A companion to philosophy of law and legal theory’, in. Malden: Wiley-Blackwell. Available at: http://dx.doi.org/10.1002/9781444320114.
Quinton, A. (1967) ‘chs. 21 and 22; reprinted as ‘Two Concepts of Democracy in Political philosophy’, in. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Rawls, J. (1999) ‘Chapter VII sections 55-59’, in A theory of justice. Rev. ed. Cambridge, Mass: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.
Raz, J. (2009) The authority of law: essays on law and morality. 2nd ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Richard B. Friedman (1990) ‘On the Concept of Authority in Political Philosophy’, in Authority. New York: New York University Press, pp. 56–91.
Richard J. Arneson (2003) ‘Defending the Purely Instrumental Account of Democratic Legitimacy’, Journal of Political Philosophy, 11(1), pp. 122–132. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-9760.00170.
Roberts, A. and Garton Ash, T. (2011) Civil resistance and power politics: the experience of non-violent action from Gandhi to the present. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Sabl, A. (2001) ‘Looking Forward to Justice: Rawlsian Civil Disobedience and its Non-Rawlsian Lessons’, Journal of Political Philosophy, 9(3), pp. 307–330. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-9760.00129.
Sanders, J.T., Narveson, J. and Simmons, A.J. (1996) ‘Philosophical Anarchism in For and against the state: new philosophical readings’, in. Lanham, Md: Rowman & Littlefield.
Sanders, J.T., Narveson, J. and Wolff, J. (1996) ‘Anarchism and Skepticism’ in For and against the state: new philosophical readings’, in. Lanham, Md: Rowman & Littlefield.
Scheffler, S. (2001) ‘Individual Responsibility in a Global Age’, in Boundaries and allegiances: problems of justice and responsibility in liberal thought. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Available at: http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/0199257671.001.0001.
Sheehy, P. (2002) ‘A Duty Not to Vote’, Ratio, 15(1), pp. 46–57. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-9329.00175.
Shelby, T. (2016) Dark ghettos: injustice, dissent, and reform. Cambridge, Massachusetts: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.
Shute, S., Hurley, S.L. and Elster, J. (1993) ‘Majority rule and individual rights’ in On human rights: the Oxford Amnesty lectures 1993’, in. New York: Basic Books.
Simmons, A.J. (1979a) ‘ch. VIII Moral principles and political obligations’, in. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press.
Simmons, A.J. (1979b) Moral principles and political obligations. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press.
Simmons, A.J. (2001) ‘Fair Play and Political Obligation: Twenty Years Later’, in Justification and legitimacy: essays on rights and obligations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Singer, P. (1973a) Democracy and disobedience. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Singer, P. (1973b) Democracy and disobedience. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Sofia Näsström (2011) ‘The Challenge of the All-Affected Principle’, Political Studies, 59(1), pp. 116–134. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9248.2010.00845.x.
Swift, A. (2006) Political philosophy: a beginners’ guide for students and politicians. 2nd ed., rev.expanded. Cambridge: Polity.
Ted. Honderich Ted Honderich (no date) Violence for equality : inquiries in political philosophy / Ted Honderich. Available at: http://ucl-primo.hosted.exlibrisgroup.com/primo_library/libweb/action/display.do?tabs=detailsTab&ct=display&fn=search&doc=UCL_LMS_DS000079578&indx=1&recIds=UCL_LMS_DS000079578&recIdxs=0&elementId=0&renderMode=poppedOut&displayMode=full&frbrVersion=&frbg=&&dscnt=0&scp.scps=scope%3A%28UCL%29%2Cprimo_central_multiple_fe&tb=t&mode=Basic&vid=UCL_VU1&srt=rank&tab=local&dum=true&vl(freeText0)=Violence%20for%20Equality%3A%20Inquiries%20in%20Political%20Philosophy&dstmp=1501678797980.
Thomas, Christiano (2001) ‘Democracy as Equality’, in David, Estlund (ed.) Democracy. Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 31–50. Available at: https://contentstore.cla.co.uk/secure/link?id=ab47e4c3-5ba1-ed11-ac20-0050f2f06092.
Thomas Christiano (2004) ‘The Authority of Democracy’, Journal of Political Philosophy, 12(3), pp. 266–290. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9760.2004.00200.x.
Thomas E. Hill, (1973) ‘Servility and Self-Respect’, Monist, 57(1), pp. 87–104. Available at: https://doi.org/10.5840/monist197357135.
Thomas E. Jr Hill (1991) ‘Symbolic protest and calculated silence’, in Autonomy and self-respect. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 52–66. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511609237.
Thoreau, H.D. (1849) Civil Disobedience. Available at: https://www.walden.org/web/viewer.html?file=https://www.walden.org/wp-content/uploads/2016/03/CivilDisobedience.pdf.
Tommie Shelby (2007) ‘Justice, Deviance, and the Dark Ghetto’, Philosophy & Public Affairs, 35(2), pp. 126–160. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1088-4963.2007.00106.x.
Vinit Haksar (1976) ‘Rawls and Gandhi on civil disobedience’, Inquiry, 19(1–4), pp. 151–192. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1080/00201747608601790.
Vinit Haksar (2012) ‘Violence in a spirit of love: Gandhi and the limits of non-violence’, Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy, 15(3), pp. 303–324. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1080/13698230.2011.644422.
Vittorio Bufacchi (2007) ‘Exploitation, Injustice and Violence’, in Violence and social justice. Houndmills, Basingstoke, Hampshire: Palgrave Macmillan, pp. 145–163. Available at: https://link.springer.com/chapter/10.1057/9780230246416_9.
Waldron, J. (1999a) ‘Part III in Law and disagreement’, in. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Waldron, J. (1999b) ‘The Constitutional Conception of Democracy’, in Law and disagreement. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198262138.001.0001.
Waldron, J. (2006) ‘The Core of the Case against Judicial Review’, Yale Law Journal [Preprint]. Available at: http://heinonline.org/HOL/Page?public=false&handle=hein.journals/ylr115&id=1366.
Walzer, M. (1970a) ‘Part 1 in Obligations: essays on disobedience’, in Obligations: essays on disobedience, war, and citizenship. Cambridge (Mass.): Harvard University Press.
Walzer, M. (1970b) ‘The Obligation to Disobey’ and ‘“The Obligations of Oppressed Minorities” in Obligations: essays on disobedience, war, and citizenship’, in. Cambridge (Mass.): Harvard University Press.
Weale, A. (2007a) ‘Chapter 1 in Democracy’, in. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.
Weale, A. (2007b) ‘Chapter 8 in Democracy’, in. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.
Wolff, R.P. (1976) ‘'The Conflict Between Authority and Autonomy’ (Part One of his book In Defense of Anarchism)’, in. New York: Harper & Row. Available at: http://www.ditext.com/wolff/anarchy.html.
Young, I.M. (2011) ‘The Social Connection Model’, in Responsibility for Justice. Oxford University Press. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780195392388.001.0001.