A. John Simmons. (1976a). Tacit Consent and Political Obligation. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 5(3), 274–291. http://www.jstor.org.libproxy.ucl.ac.uk/stable/2264884?seq=1#page_scan_tab_contents
A. John Simmons. (1976b). Tacit Consent and Political Obligation. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 5(3), 274–291. http://www.jstor.org.libproxy.ucl.ac.uk/stable/2264884?seq=1#page_scan_tab_contents
A. John Simmons. (1996). Associative Political Obligations. Ethics, 106(2), 247–273. http://www.jstor.org/stable/2382059
A. John Simmons. (2000a). Fair Play and Political Obligation: Twenty Years Later. In Justification and Legitimacy. Cambridge University Press. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511625152
A. John Simmons. (2000b). Fair Play and Political Obligation: Twenty Years Later. In Justification and Legitimacy. Cambridge University Press. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511625152
A. John Simmons. (1999). Justification and Legitimacy*. Ethics, 109(4), 739–771. http://www.jstor.org/stable/10.1086/233944
Adam, J. & Plato. (1903). Platonis Crito: Vol. Pitt press series. University press.
Alan Patten. (2002). Democratic Secession from a Multinational State*. Ethics, 112(3), 558–586. http://www.jstor.org/stable/10.1086/338778
Allen Buchanan. (2002). Political Legitimacy and Democracy*. Ethics, 112(4), 689–719. http://www.jstor.org/stable/10.1086/340313
Andrew Mason. (1997). Special Obligations to Compatriots. Ethics, 107(3), 427–447. http://www.jstor.org/stable/2382324
Anne Phillips. (1997). Democracy and Difference: Some Problems for Feminist Theory. In The rights of minority cultures. Oxford University Press.
Arneson, R. J. (2003). Defending the Purely Instrumental Account of Democratic Legitimacy. Journal of Political Philosophy, 11(1), 122–132. https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-9760.00170
Beitz, C. R. (1989). Political equality: an essay in democratic theory. Princeton University Press.
Beran, H. (n.d.). The consent theory of political obligation: Vol. Croom Helm international series in social and political thought. Croom Helm.
Brettschneider, C. (2005). Balancing Procedures and Outcomes Within Democratic Theory: Core Values and Judicial Review. Political Studies, 53(2), 423–441. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9248.2005.00536.x
Brian Barry. (1991). Is Democracy Special? In Democracy and power: essays in political theory I. Clarendon Press.
Brilmayer, Lea. (1991). Secession and Self-Determination: A Territorial Interpretation. Yale Journal of International Law, 16(1), 177–202. http://www.heinonline.org/HOL/Page?handle=hein.journals/yjil16&id=183&collection=journals&index=journals/yjil
Brownlee, K. (2004). Features of a Paradigm Case of Civil Disobedience. Res Publica, 10(4), 337–351. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11158-004-2326-6
Brownlee, K. (2012). Conscience and Conviction. Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199592944.001.0001
BUCHANAN, A. (1997). Theories of Secession. Philosophy  Public Affairs, 26(1), 31–61. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1088-4963.1997.tb00049.x
Buchanan, A. (2003). Justice, Legitimacy, and Self-Determination. Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/0198295359.001.0001
Buchanan, A. E. (1991). Secession: the morality of political divorce from Fort Sumter to Lithuania and Quebec. Westview Press.
Cabrera, Luis. (1 C.E.). The Inconveniences of Transnational Democracy. Ethics and International Affairs, 21(2), 219–238. https://www.cambridge.org/core/journals/ethics-and-international-affairs/article/inconveniences-of-transnational-democracy/96027C6EE6E68D572DE43E93F9E2C8A8
Christiano, T. (1996). The rule of the many: fundamental issues in democratic theory: Vol. Focus (Southern Regional Education Board). Westview Press.
Christiano, T. (2004a). The Authority of Democracy*. Journal of Political Philosophy, 12(3), 266–290. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9760.2004.00200.x
Christiano, T. (2004b). The Authority of Democracy*. Journal of Political Philosophy, 12(3), 266–290. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9760.2004.00200.x
Christiano, T. (2008). The Constitution of Equality. Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198297475.001.0001
Christopher H. Wellman. (1995). A Defense of Secession and Political Self-Determination. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 24(2), 142–171. http://www.jstor.org/stable/2265391
Christopher Heath Wellman. (1997). Associative Allegiances and Political Obligations. Social Theory and Practice, 23(2), 181–204. http://www.jstor.org/stable/23559181
Dagger, R. (2000a). Membership, Fair Play, and Political Obligation. Political Studies, 48(1), 104–117. https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-9248.00253
Dagger, R. (2000b). Membership, Fair Play, and Political Obligation. Political Studies, 48(1), 104–117. https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-9248.00253
Dahl, R. A. (1989a). Democracy and its critics. Yale University Press. https://search.ebscohost.com/login.aspx?direct=true&AuthType=ip,shib&db=nlebk&AN=52831&site=ehost-live&scope=site&custid=s8454451
Dahl, R. A. (1989b). Democracy and its critics. Yale University Press. https://search.ebscohost.com/login.aspx?direct=true&AuthType=ip,shib&db=nlebk&AN=52831&site=ehost-live&scope=site&custid=s8454451
Daniel Philpott. (1995). In Defense of Self-Determination. Ethics, 105(2), 352–385. http://www.jstor.org/stable/2382349
Daniel Star & Candice Delmas. (n.d.-a). Three Conceptions of Practical Authority. Jurisprudence, 21(2), 143–160. https://doi.org/10.5235/204033211796290272
Daniel Star & Candice Delmas. (n.d.-b). Three Conceptions of Practical Authority. Jurisprudence, 21(2), 143–160. https://doi.org/10.5235/204033211796290272
Darwall, S. (2011). Authority, Accountability, and Preemption. Jurisprudence, 2(1), 103–119. https://doi.org/10.5235/204033211796290263
David Enoch. (2002). Some Arguments against Conscientious Objection and Civil Disobedience Refuted. Israel Law Review, 36, 227–253. http://www.heinonline.org/HOL/Page?handle=hein.journals/israel36&id=629&collection=journals&index=journals/israel
David Gauthier. (1994). Breaking up: An Essay on Secession. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 24(3), 357–371. http://www.jstor.org/stable/40231872
David Held. (1995). Democracy and the International System. In Cosmopolitan democracy: an agenda for a new world order. Polity Press.
David Miller. (1998). Secession and the Principle of Nationality. In M. Moore (Ed.), National Self-Determination and Secession. Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/0198293844.001.0001
David Miller. (2010). Against Global Democracy. In After the nation?: critical reflections on nationalism and post-nationalism: Vol. International political theory series. Palgrave Macmillan.
David Lefkowitz. (2007). On a Moral Right to Civil Disobedience*. Ethics, 117(2), 202–233. http://www.jstor.org/stable/10.1086/510694
Democracy, Political Equality, and Majority Rule*. (2010). Ethics, 121(1), 148–177. http://www.jstor.org/stable/10.1086/656474
Democracy (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy). (n.d.). http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/democracy/
Dworkin, R. (1986a). Civil disobedience and nuclear protest. In A matter of principle. Clarendon Press.
Dworkin, R. (1986b). Civil disobedience and nuclear protest. In A matter of principle. Clarendon Press.
Dworkin, R. (1986c). Law’s empire: Vol. Fontana master guides. Fontana.
Dworkin, R. (1986d). Law’s empire: Vol. Fontana master guides. Fontana.
Dworkin, R. (2011). Justice for hedgehogs. Belknap Press of Harvard University Press. https://search-ebscohost-com.libproxy.ucl.ac.uk/login.aspx?direct=true&AuthType=ip,shib&db=nlebk&AN=364811&site=ehost-live&scope=site&custid=s8454451
Estlund, D. M. (2001). Democracy: Vol. Blackwell readings in philosophy. Blackwell Publishers.
Estlund, D. M. (2008). Democratic authority: a philosophical framework [David m. estlund]. Princeton University Press. http://www.vlebooks.com/vleweb/product/openreader?id=UCL&isbn=9781400831548
George Klosko. (1987). Presumptive Benefit, Fairness, and Political Obligation. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 16(3), 241–259. http://www.jstor.org/stable/2265266
George Klosko. (2004). Multiple Principles of Political Obligation. Political Theory, 32(6), 801–824. http://www.jstor.org/stable/4148146
GOODIN, R. E. (2007). Enfranchising All Affected Interests, and Its Alternatives. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 35(1), 40–68. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1088-4963.2007.00098.x
Goodin, R. E. (2010). Global democracy: in the beginning. International Theory, 2(02), 175–209. https://doi.org/10.1017/S1752971910000060
Goodin, R. E., Pettit, P., & Pogge, T. (Eds.). (2017). A Companion to Contemporary Political Philosophy. Wiley. https://doi.org/10.1002/9781405177245
Gordon Graham. (1983). What is Special About Democracy? Mind, 92(365), 94–102. http://www.jstor.org/stable/2253932
Gould, C. C. (2004). Globalizing democracy and human rights. Cambridge University Press. https://doi-org.libproxy.ucl.ac.uk/10.1017/CBO9780511617096
Green, L. (1988). The authority of the state. Clarendon.
Griffin, C. G. (2003). Democracy as a Non-Instrumentally Just Procedure. Journal of Political Philosophy, 11(1), 111–121. https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-9760.00169
Gutmann, A. (2017). Democracy. In R. E. Goodin, P. Pettit, & T. Pogge (Eds.), A Companion to Contemporary Political Philosophy. Wiley. https://doi.org/10.1002/9781405177245
Haksar, V. (1976). Rawls and Gandhi on civil disobedience. Inquiry, 19(1–4), 151–192. https://doi.org/10.1080/00201747608601790
Hanna Pitkin. (1966a). Obligation and Consent--II. The American Political Science Review, 60(1), 39–52. http://www.jstor.org.libproxy.ucl.ac.uk/stable/1953805?origin=crossref&seq=1#page_scan_tab_contents
Hanna Pitkin. (1966b). Obligation and Consent--II. The American Political Science Review, 60(1), 39–52. http://www.jstor.org.libproxy.ucl.ac.uk/stable/1953805?origin=crossref&seq=1#page_scan_tab_contents
Harrison, R. (2002). Democracy. Routledge. https://doi.org/10.4324/9780203005545
Harry G. Frankfurt. (1973). The Anarchism of Robert Paul Wolff. Political Theory, 1(4), 405–414. http://www.jstor.org/stable/191060
Horton, J. (1992a). Political obligation: Vol. Issues in political theory. Macmillan.
Horton, J. (1992b). Political obligation: Vol. Issues in political theory. Macmillan.
Horton, J. (2006). In Defence of Associative Political Obligations: Part One. Political Studies, 54(3), 427–443. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9248.2006.00621.x
Horton, J. (2007). In Defence of Associative Political Obligations: Part Two. Political Studies, 55(1), 1–19. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9248.2007.00642.x
Hume, D., & MacIntyre, A. C. (1979). Hume’s ethical writings: selections from David Hume. University of Notre Dame Press.
Jeremy Waldron. (1995). The Wisdom of the Multitude: Some Reflections on Book 3, Chapter 11 of Aristotle’s Politics. Political Theory, 23(4), 563–584. http://www.jstor.org/stable/191901
Jeremy Waldron. (2006). The Core of the Case against Judicial Review. The Yale Law Journal, 115(6), 1346–1406. http://www.jstor.org/stable/10.2307/20455656?origin=crossref
Jo Wolff. (1996). Anarchism and Skepticism. In For and against the state: new philosophical readings: Vol. Studies in social, political, and legal philosophy. Rowman & Littlefield.
Jo Wolff. (2000). Political Obligation: A Pluralistic Approach. In Pluralism: the philosophy and politics of diversity. Routledge.
JOHN  MORREALL. (2013a). The Justifiability of Violent Civil Disobedience. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 6(1), 35–47. http://www-tandfonline-com.libproxy.ucl.ac.uk/doi/abs/10.1080/00455091.1976.10716975
JOHN  MORREALL. (2013b). The Justifiability of Violent Civil Disobedience. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 6(1), 35–47. http://www-tandfonline-com.libproxy.ucl.ac.uk/doi/abs/10.1080/00455091.1976.10716975
John Horton. (1992a). Chapters 2,3,4,. In Political obligation: Vol. Issues in political theory. Macmillan.
John Horton. (1992b). Chapters 2,3,4,. In Political obligation: Vol. Issues in political theory. Macmillan.
John Rawls. (1999). Legal Obligation and the Duty of Fair Play. In Collected papers. Harvard University Press.
John Simmons. (1996). Philosophical Anarchism. In For and against the state: new philosophical readings: Vol. Studies in social, political, and legal philosophy. Rowman & Littlefield.
Joseph Raz. (1985). Authority and Justification. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 14(1), 3–29. http://www.jstor.org/stable/2265235
Joshua Cohen. (1989). Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy. In The Good polity: normative analysis of the state. Basil Blackwell.
Klosko, G. (2004). The principle of fairness and political obligation: Vol. Studies in social, political, and legal philosophy (New ed). Rowman & Littlefield.
Koenig-Archibugi, M. (2011). Is global democracy possible? European Journal of International Relations, 17(3), 519–542. https://doi.org/10.1177/1354066110366056
LIST, C. (2011). The Logical Space of Democracy. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 39(3), 262–297. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1088-4963.2011.01206.x
LIST, C., & KOENIG-ARCHIBUGI, M. (2010). Can There Be a Global Demos? An Agency-Based Approach. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 38(1), 76–110. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1088-4963.2009.01174.x
Locke, J., Locke, J., & Gough, J. W. (1948). The second treatise of civil government: and, A letter concerning toleration. Basil Blackwell.
LYONS, D. (1998). Moral Judgment, Historical Reality, and Civil Disobedience. Philosophy  Public Affairs, 27(1), 31–49. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1088-4963.1998.tb00058.x
Macdonald, T. (2008). Global Stakeholder Democracy. Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199235001.001.0001
Macedo, S., & Buchanan, A. E. (2003). Secession and self-determination: Vol. Nomos. New York University Press.
Margaret Moore. (n.d.). The Ethics of Secession and a Normative Theory of Nationalism. Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence, 13(2), 225–250. http://www.heinonline.org/HOL/Page?handle=hein.journals/caljp13&id=227&collection=journals&index=journals/caljp
Margaret Gilbert. (1999). Reconsidering the ‘Actual Contract’ and Theory of Political Obligation*. Ethics, 109(2), 236–260. http://www.jstor.org/stable/10.1086/233895
Markovitz, D. (2005a). ‘Democratic Disobedience’. Yale Law Journal, 114. https://digitalcommons.law.yale.edu/fss_papers/418/
Markovitz, D. (2005b). ‘Democratic Disobedience’. Yale Law Journal, 114. https://digitalcommons.law.yale.edu/fss_papers/418/
Martin L. King. (n.d.-a). Letter from Birmingham Jail. https://www.africa.upenn.edu/Articles_Gen/Letter_Birmingham.html
Martin L. King. (n.d.-b). Letter from Birmingham Jail. https://www.africa.upenn.edu/Articles_Gen/Letter_Birmingham.html
May, T. (n.d.-a). On Raz and the Obligation to Obey the Law. Law and Philosophy, 16(1), 19–36. https://www.jstor.org/stable/3504817?seq=1#metadata_info_tab_contents
May, T. (n.d.-b). On Raz and the Obligation to Obey the Law. Law and Philosophy, 16(1), 19–36. https://www.jstor.org/stable/3504817?seq=1#metadata_info_tab_contents
McDermott, D. (2004). Fair-Play Obligations. Political Studies, 52(2), 216–232. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9248.2004.00476.x
Miller, D. (1984). Anarchism: Vol. Modern ideologies. Dent.
Miller, D. (2009). Democracy’s Domain. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 37(3), 201–228. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1088-4963.2009.01158.x
Moore, M. (Ed.). (1998a). National Self-Determination and Secession. Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/0198293844.001.0001
Moore, M. (Ed.). (1998b). National Self-Determination and Secession. Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/0198293844.001.0001
Näsström, S. (2011). The Challenge of the All-Affected Principle. Political Studies, 59(1), 116–134. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9248.2010.00845.x
Noveck, Scott M. (2007). Is Judicial Review Compatible with Democracy? Cardozo Public Law, Policy, and Ethics Journal, 6(2), 401–430. http://www.heinonline.org/HOL/Page?handle=hein.journals/cardplp6&id=407&collection=journals&index=journals/cardplp
Nozick, R. (1974). Anarchy, state, and utopia. Blackwell.
Parijs, P. (1996). Justice and Democracy: Are they Incompatible?*. Journal of Political Philosophy, 4(2), 101–117. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9760.1996.tb00044.x
Pateman, C. (1985). The problem of political obligation: a critique of liberal theory. Polity in association with Blackwell.
Patrick Durning. (2003). Joseph Raz and the Instrumental Justification of a Duty to Obey the Law. Law and Philosophy, 22(6), 597–620. http://www.jstor.org/stable/3505046
Pitkin, H. (1965). Obligation and Consent--I. The American Political Science Review, 59(4). https://doi.org/10.2307/1953218
Quinton, A. (1967). Political philosophy: Vol. Oxford readings in philosophy. Oxford University Press.
Rawls, J. (1999). A theory of justice (Rev. ed). Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.
Raz, J. (1979). The authority of lawEssays on law and morality. Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198253457.001.0001
Review by: Joshua Cohen. (1986). Reflections on Rousseau: Autonomy and Democracy. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 15(3), 275–297. http://www.jstor.org/stable/2265213
Richard Arneson. (2004). Democracy is not Intrinsically Just. In Justice and democracy: essays for Brian Barry. Cambridge University Press.
Richard B. Friedman. (1992). On the Concept of Authority in Political Philosophy. In Political obligation: Vol. Issues in political theory. Macmillan.
Richard Dworkin. (1998). The Puzzle of Legitimacy’. In Law’s empire. Hart.
Richard J. Arneson. (1982). The Principle of Fairness and Free-Rider Problems. Ethics, 92(4), 616–633. http://www.jstor.org/stable/2380394
Richard Tuck. (1972). Why is Authority Such a Problem? In Philosophy, politics and society: 4th series. Blackwell.
Ripstein, A. (2004). Authority and Coercion. Philosophy  Public Affairs, 32(1), 2–35. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-6486.2004.00003.x
Risse, M. (2004). Arguing for Majority Rule*. Journal of Political Philosophy, 12(1), 41–64. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9760.2004.00190.x
Robert Dahl. (1999). Can International Organisations be Democratic? In Democracy’s edges: Vol. Contemporary political theory. Cambridge University Press.
Robert P. Wolff. (1976). The Conflict Between Authority and Autonomy’. In In defense of anarchism: Vol. Harper essays in philosophy. Harper & Row.
Ronald Dworkin. (1973a). The Original Position. The University of Chicago Law Review, 40(3), 500–533. http://www.jstor.org.libproxy.ucl.ac.uk/stable/1599246?origin=crossref&seq=1#page_scan_tab_contents
Ronald Dworkin. (1973b). The Original Position. The University of Chicago Law Review, 40(3), 500–533. http://www.jstor.org.libproxy.ucl.ac.uk/stable/1599246?origin=crossref&seq=1#page_scan_tab_contents
Ronald Dworkin. (1977). Civil Disobedience. In Taking rights seriously. Duckworth.
Ross, M. (2006). Is Democracy Good for the Poor? American Journal of Political Science, 50(4), 860–874. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1540-5907.2006.00220.x
Sabl, A. (2001). Looking Forward to Justice: Rawlsian Civil Disobedience and its Non-Rawlsian Lessons. Journal of Political Philosophy, 9(3), 331–349. https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-9760.00129
Schumpeter, J. A. (1943). Capitalism, socialism, and democracy. G. Allen & Unwin Ltd.
Sen, A. K. (1999). Democracy as a Universal Value. Journal of Democracy, 10(3), 3–17. https://doi.org/10.1353/jod.1999.0055
Simmons, A. J. (1979a). Moral principles and political obligations. Princeton University Press.
Simmons, A. J. (1979b). Moral principles and political obligations. Princeton University Press.
Simmons, A. J. (1979c). Moral principles and political obligations. Princeton University Press.
Simmons, A. J. (1979d). Moral principles and political obligations. Princeton University Press.
Singer, P. (1973). Democracy and disobedience. Clarendon Press.
Smith, W. (2004a). Democracy, Deliberation and Disobedience. Res Publica, 10(4), 353–377. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11158-004-2327-5
Smith, W. (2004b). Democracy, Deliberation and Disobedience. Res Publica, 10(4), 353–377. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11158-004-2327-5
Steven Macedo. (n.d.). Against Majoritarianism: Democratic Values and Institutional Design. Boston University Law Review, 90(2), 1029–1042. http://www.heinonline.org/HOL/Page?page=1029&handle=hein.journals%2Fbulr90&collection=journals
Tamir, Y. (1993). Liberal nationalism: Vol. Studies in moral, political, and legal philosophy. Princeton University Press.
Thompson, D. F. (1999). Democratic Theory and Global Society. Journal of Political Philosophy, 7(2), 111–125. https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-9760.00069
Valentini, L. (2013). Justice, Disagreement and Democracy. British Journal of Political Science, 43(01), 177–199. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0007123412000294
W. B. Gallie. (1956a). Essentially Contested Concepts. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 56, 167–198. http://www.jstor.org.libproxy.ucl.ac.uk/stable/4544562?seq=1#page_scan_tab_contents
W. B. Gallie. (1956b). Essentially Contested Concepts. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 56, 167–198. http://www.jstor.org.libproxy.ucl.ac.uk/stable/4544562?seq=1#page_scan_tab_contents
Waldron, J. (1999). Law and Disagreement. Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198262138.001.0001
Walzer, M. (1970). Obligations: essays on disobedience, war, and citizenship. Harvard University Press.
Walzer, M. (1983). Spheres of justice: a defense of pluralism and equality. Basic Books.
Weale, A. (1999a). Democracy: Vol. Issues in political theory. Palgrave.
Weale, A. (1999b). Democracy: Vol. Issues in political theory. Palgrave.
Wellman, C. H. (2005). A theory of secession: the case for political self-determination. Cambridge University Press. https://www-cambridge-org.libproxy.ucl.ac.uk/core/books/theory-of-secession/79CF1B218C8B49C0EBC9E1493DB75ED7
Wolff, J. (2006). An introduction to political philosophy (Rev. ed). Oxford University Press.
Young, I. M. (2002). Inclusion and Democracy. Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/0198297556.001.0001